Abortion and the Social Contract
See the Appendix - Arguments from the Right to Life
The issue of abortion is emotionally loaded and this often makes for poor
not thoroughly thought out arguments. The questions: "Is abortion immoral" and "Is abortion a murder" are often confused. The pregnancy (and the resulting fetus) are discussed in terms normally reserved to natural catastrophes (force majeure). At times
the embryo is compared to cancer
a thief
or an invader: after all
they are both growths
clusters of cells. The difference
of course
is that no one contracts cancer willingly (except
to some extent
smokers -–but
then they gamble
not contract).
When a woman engages in voluntary sex
does not use contraceptives and gets pregnant – one can say that she signed a contract with her fetus. A contract entails the demonstrated existence of a reasonably (and reasonable) free will. If the fulfillment of the obligations in a contract between individuals could be life-threatening – it is fair and safe to assume that no rational free will was involved. No reasonable person would sign or enter such a contract with another person (though most people would sign such contracts with society).
Judith Jarvis Thomson argued convincingly ("A Defence of Abortion") that pregnancies that are the result of forced sex (rape being a special case) or which are life threatening should or could
morally
be terminated. Using the transactional language: the contract was not entered to willingly or reasonably and
therefore
is null and void. Any actions which are intended to terminate it and to annul its consequences should be legally and morally permissible.
The same goes for a contract which was entered into against the express will of one of the parties and despite all the reasonable measures that the unwilling party adopted to prevent it. If a mother uses contraceptives in a manner intended to prevent pregnancy
it is as good as saying: " I do not want to sign this contract
I am doing my reasonable best not to sign it
if it is signed – it is contrary to my express will". There is little legal (or moral) doubt that such a contract should be voided.
Much more serious problems arise when we study the other party to these implicit agreements: the embryo. To start with
it lacks consciousness (in the sense that is needed for signing an enforceable and valid contract). Can a contract be valid even if one of the "signatories" lacks this sine qua non trait? In the absence of consciousness
there is little point in talking about free will (or rights which depend on sentience). So
is the contract not a contract at all? Does it not reflect the intentions of the parties?
The answer is in the negative. The contract between a mother and her fetus is derived from the larger Social Contract. Society – through its apparatuses – stands for the embryo the same way that it represents minors
the mentally retarded
and the insane. Society steps in – and has the recognized right and moral obligation to do so – whenever the powers of the parties to a contract (implicit or explicit) are not balanced. It protects small citizens from big monopolies
the physically weak from the thug
the tiny opposition from the mighty administration
the barely surviving radio station from the claws of the devouring state mechanism. It also has the right and obligation to intervene
intercede and represent the unconscious: this is why euthanasia is absolutely forbidden without the consent of the dying person. There is not much difference between the embryo and the comatose.
A typical contract states the rights of the parties. It assumes the existence of parties which are "moral personhoods" or "morally significant persons" – in other words
persons who are holders of rights and can demand from us to respect these rights. Contracts explicitly elaborate some of these rights and leaves others unmentioned because of the presumed existence of the Social Contract. The typical contract assumes that there is a social contract which applies to the parties to the contract and which is universally known and
therefore
implicitly incorporated in every contract. Thus
an explicit contract can deal with the property rights of a certain person
while neglecting to mention that person's rights to life
to free speech
to the enjoyment the fruits of his lawful property and
in general to a happy life.
There is little debate that the Mother is a morally significant person and that she is a rights-holder. All born humans are and
more so
all adults above a certain age. But what about the unborn fetus?
One approach is that the embryo has no rights until certain conditions are met and only upon their fulfillment is he transformed into a morally significant person ("moral agent"). Opinions differ as to what are the conditions. Rationality
or a morally meaningful and valued life are some of the oft cited criteria. The fallaciousness of this argument is easy to demonstrate: children are irrational – is this a licence to commit infanticide?
A second approach says that a person has the right to life because it desires it.
But then what about chronic depressives who wish to die – do we have the right to terminate their miserable lives? The good part of life (and
therefore
the differential and meaningful test) is in the experience itself – not in the desire to experience.
Another variant says that a person has the right to life because once his life is terminated – his experiences cease. So
how should we judge the right to life of someone who constantly endures bad experiences (and
as a result
harbors a death wish)? Should he better be "terminated"?
Having reviewed the above arguments and counter-arguments
Don Marquis goes on (in "Why Abortion is Immoral"
1989
to offer a sharper and more comprehensive criterion: terminating a life is morally wrong because a person has a future filled with value and meaning
similar to ours.
But the whole debate is unnecessary. There is no conflict between the rights of the mother and those of her fetus because there is never a conflict between parties to an agreement. By signing an agreement
the mother gave up some of her rights and limited the others. This is normal practice in contracts: they represent compromises
the optimization (and not the maximization) of the parties' rights and wishes. The rights of the fetus are an inseparable part of the contract which the mother signed voluntarily and reasonably. They are derived from the mother's behaviour. Getting willingly pregnant (or assuming the risk of getting pregnant by not using contraceptives reasonably) – is the behaviour which validates and ratifies a contract between her and the fetus. Many contracts are by behaviour
rather than by a signed piece of paper. Numerous contracts are verbal or behavioural. These contracts
though implicit
are as binding as any of their written
more explicit
brethren. Legally (and morally) the situation is crystal clear: the mother signed some of her rights away in this contract. Even if she regrets it – she cannot claim her rights back by annulling the contract unilaterally. No contract can be annulled this way – the consent of both parties is required. Many times we realize that we have entered a bad contract
but there is nothing much that we can do about it. These are the rules of the game.
Thus the two remaining questions: (a) can this specific contract (pregnancy) be annulled and
if so (b) in which circumstances – can be easily settled using modern contract law. Yes
a contract can be annulled and voided if signed under duress
involuntarily
by incompetent persons (e.g.
the insane)
or if one of the parties made a reasonable and full scale attempt to prevent its signature
thus expressing its clear will not to sign the contract. It is also terminated or voided if it would be unreasonable to expect one of the parties to see it through. Rape
contraception failure
life threatening situations are all such cases.
This could be argued against by saying that
in the case of economic hardship
f or instance
the damage to the mother's future is certain. True
her value- filled
meaningful future is granted – but so is the detrimental effect that the fetus will have on it
once born. This certainty cannot be balanced by the UNCERTAIN value-filled future life of the embryo. Always
preferring an uncertain good to a certain evil is morally wrong. But surely this is a quantitative matter – not a qualitative one. Certain
limited aspects of the rest of the mother's life will be adversely effected (and can be ameliorated by society's helping hand and intervention) if she does have the baby. The decision not to have it is both qualitatively and qualitatively different. It is to deprive the unborn of all the aspects of all his future life – in which he might well have experienced happiness
values
and meaning.
The questions whether the fetus is a Being or a growth of cells
conscious in any manner
or utterly unconscious
able to value his life and to want them – are all but irrelevant. He has the potential to lead a happy
meaningful
value-filled life
similar to ours
very much as a one minute old baby does. The contract between him and his mother is a service provision contract. She provides him with goods and services that he requires in order to materialize his potential. It sounds very much like many other human contracts. And this contract continue well after pregnancy has ended and birth given.
Consider education: children do not appreciate its importance or value its potential – still
it is enforced upon them because we
who are capable of those feats
want them to have the tools that they will need in order to develop their potential. In this and many other respects
the human pregnancy continues well into the fourth year of life (physiologically it continues in to the second year of life - see "Born Alien"). Should the location of the pregnancy (in uterus
in vivo) determine its future? If a mother has the right to abort at will
why should the mother be denied her right to terminate the " pregnancy" AFTER the fetus emerges and the pregnancy continues OUTSIDE her womb? Even after birth
the woman's body is the main source of food to the baby and
in any case
she has to endure physical hardship to raise the child. Why not extend the woman's ownership of her body and right to it further in time and space to the post-natal period?
Contracts to provide goods and services (always at a personal cost to the provider) are the commonest of contracts. We open a business. We sell a software application
we publish a book – we engage in helping others to materialize their potential. We should always do so willingly and reasonably – otherwise the contracts that we sign will be null and void. But to deny anyone his capacity to materialize his potential and the goods and services that he needs to do so – after a valid contract was entered into - is immoral. To refuse to provide a service or to condition it provision (Mother: " I will provide the goods and services that I agreed to provide to this fetus under this contract only if and when I benefit from such provision") is a violation of the contract and should be penalized. Admittedly
at times we have a right to choose to do the immoral (because it has not been codified as illegal) – but that does not turn it into moral.
Still
not every immoral act involving the termination of life can be classified as murder. Phenomenology is deceiving: the acts look the same (cessation of life functions
the prevention of a future). But murder is the intentional termination of the life of a human who possesses
at the moment of death
a consciousness (and
in most cases
a free will
especially the will not to die). Abortion is the intentional termination of a life which has the potential to develop into a person with consciousness and free will. Philosophically
no identity can be established between potential and actuality. The destruction of paints and cloth is not tantamount (not to say identical) to the destruction of a painting by Van Gogh
made up of these very elements. Paints and cloth are converted to a painting through the intermediacy and agency of the Painter. A cluster of cells a human makes only through the agency of Nature. Surely
the destruction of the painting materials constitutes an offence against the Painter. In the same way
the destruction of the fetus constitutes an offence against Nature. But there is no denying that in both cases
no finished product was eliminated. Naturally
this becomes less and less so (the severity of the terminating act increases) as the process of creation advances.
Classifying an abortion as murder poses numerous and insurmountable philosophical problems.
No one disputes the now common view that the main crime committed in aborting a pregnancy – is a crime against potentialities. If so
what is the philosophical difference between aborting a fetus and destroying a sperm and an egg? These two contain all the information (=all the potential) and their destruction is philosophically no less grave than the destruction of a fetus. The destruction of an egg and a sperm is even more serious philosophically: the creation of a fetus limits the set of all potentials embedded in the genetic material to the one fetus created. The egg and sperm can be compared to the famous wave function (state vector) in quantum mechanics – the represent millions of potential final states (=millions of potential embryos and lives). The fetus is the collapse of the wave function: it represents a much more limited set of potentials. If killing an embryo is murder because of the elimination of potentials – how should we consider the intentional elimination of many more potentials through masturbation and contraception?
The argument that it is difficult to say which sperm cell will impregnate the egg is not serious. Biologically
it does not matter – they all carry the same genetic content. Moreover
would this counter-argument still hold if
in future
we were be able to identify the chosen one and eliminate only it? In many religions (Catholicism) contraception is murder. In Judaism
masturbation is "the corruption of the seed" and such a serious offence that it is punishable by the strongest religious penalty: eternal ex-communication ("Karet").
If abortion is indeed murder how should we resolve the following moral dilemmas and questions (some of them patently absurd):
Is a natural abortion the equivalent of manslaughter (through negligence)?
Do habits like smoking
drug addiction
vegetarianism – infringe upon the right to life of the embryo? Do they constitute a violation of the contract?
Reductio ad absurdum: if
in the far future
research will unequivocally prove that listening to a certain kind of music or entertaining certain thoughts seriously hampers the embryonic development – should we apply censorship to the Mother?
Should force majeure clauses be introduced to the Mother-Embryo pregnancy contract? Will they give the mother the right to cancel the contract? Will the embryo have a right to terminate the contract? Should the asymmetry persist: the Mother will have no right to terminate – but the embryo will
or vice versa?
Being a rights holder
can the embryo (=the State) litigate against his Mother or Third Parties (the doctor that aborted him
someone who hit his mother and brought about a natural abortion) even after he died?
Should anyone who knows about an abortion be considered an accomplice to murder?
If abortion is murder – why punish it so mildly? Why is there a debate regarding this question? "Thou shalt not kill" is a natural law
it appears in virtually every legal system. It is easily and immediately identifiable. The fact that abortion does not "enjoy" the same legal and moral treatment says a lot.
Appendix - Arguments from the Right to Life
I. The Right to Life
It is a fundamental principle of most moral theories that all human beings have a right to life. The existence of a right implies obligations or duties of third parties towards the right-holder. One has a right AGAINST other people. The fact that one possesses a certain right - prescribes to others certain obligatory behaviours and proscribes certain acts or omissions. This Janus-like nature of rights and duties as two sides of the same ethical coin - creates great confusion. People often and easily confuse rights and their attendant duties or obligations with the morally decent
or even with the morally permissible. What one MUST do as a result of another's right - should never be confused with one SHOULD or OUGHT to do morally (in the absence of a right).
The right to life has eight distinct strains:
IA. The right to be brought to life
IB. The right to be born
IC. The right to have one's life maintained
ID. The right not to be killed
IE. The right to have one's life saved
IF. The right to save one's life (erroneously limited to the right to self-defence)
IG. The Right to terminate one's life
IH. The right to have one's life terminated
IA. The Right to be Brought to Life
Only living people have rights. There is a debate whether an egg is a living person - but there can be no doubt that it exists. Its rights - whatever they are - derive from the fact that it exists and that it has the potential to develop life. The right to be brought to life (the right to become or to be) pertains to a yet non-alive entity and
therefore
is null and void. Had this right existed
it would have implied an obligation or duty to give life to the unborn and the not yet conceived. No such duty or obligation exist.
IB. The Right to be Born
The right to be born crystallizes at the moment of voluntary and intentional fertilization. If a woman knowingly engages in sexual intercourse for the explicit and express purpose of having a child - then the resulting fertilized egg has a right to mature and be born. Furthermore
the born child has all the rights a child has against his parents: food
shelter
emotional nourishment
education
and so on.
It is debatable whether such rights of the fetus and
later
of the child
exist if the fertilization was either involuntary (rape) or unintentional ("accidental" pregnancies). It would seem that the fetus has a right to be kept alive outside the mother's womb
if possible. But it is not clear whether it has a right to go on using the mother's body
or resources
or to burden her in any way in order to sustain its own life (see IC below).
IC. The Right to have One's Life Maintained
Does one have the right to maintain one's life and prolong them at other people's expense? Does one have the right to use other people's bodies
their property
their time
their resources and to deprive them of pleasure
comfort
material possessions
income
or any other thing?
The answer is yes and no.
No one has a right to sustain his or her life
maintain
or prolong them at another INDIVIDUAL's expense (no matter how minimal and insignificant the sacrifice required is). Still
if a contract has been signed - implicitly or explicitly - between the parties
then such a right may crystallize in the contract and create corresponding duties and obligations
moral
as well as legal.
Example:
No fetus has a right to sustain its life
maintain
or prolong them at his mother's expense (no matter how minimal and insignificant the sacrifice required of her is). Still
if she signed a contract with the fetus - by knowingly and willingly and intentionally conceiving it - such a right has crystallized and has created corresponding duties and obligations of the mother towards her fetus.
On the other hand
everyone has a right to sustain his or her life
maintain
or prolong them at SOCIETY's expense (no matter how major and significant the resources required are). Still
if a contract has been signed - implicitly or explicitly - between the parties
then the abrogation of such a right may crystallize in the contract and create corresponding duties and obligations
moral
as well as legal.
Example:
Everyone has a right to sustain his or her life
maintain
or prolong them at society's expense. Public hospitals
state pension schemes
and police forces may be required to fulfill society's obligations - but fulfill them it must
no matter how major and significant the resources are. Still
if a person volunteered to join the army and a contract has been signed between the parties
then this right has been thus abrogated and the individual assumed certain duties and obligations
including the duty or obligation to give up his or her life to society.
ID. The Right not to be Killed
Every person has the right not to be killed unjustly. What constitutes "just killing" is a matter for an ethical calculus in the framework of a social contract.
But does A's right not to be killed include the right against third parties that they refrain from enforcing the rights of other people against A? Does A's right not to be killed preclude the righting of wrongs committed by A against others - even if the righting of such wrongs means the killing of A?
Not so. There is a moral obligation to right wrongs (to restore the rights of other people). If A maintains or prolongs his life ONLY by violating the rights of others and these other people object to it - then A must be killed if that is the only way to right the wrong and re-assert their rights.
IE. The Right to have One's Life Saved
There is no such right as there is no corresponding moral obligation or duty to save a life. This "right" is a demonstration of the aforementioned muddle between the morally commendable
desirable and decent ("ought"
should
) and the morally obligatory
the result of other people's rights ("must").
In some countries
the obligation to save life is legally codified. But while the law of the land may create a LEGAL right and corresponding LEGAL obligations - it does not always or necessarily create a moral or an ethical right and corresponding moral duties and obligations.
IF. The Right to Save One's Own Life
The right to self-defence is a subset of the more general and all-pervasive right to save one's own life. One has the right to take certain actions or avoid taking certain actions in order to save his or her own life.
It is generally accepted that one has the right to kill a pursuer who knowingly and intentionally intends to take one's life. It is debatable
though
whether one has the right to kill an innocent person who unknowingly and unintentionally threatens to take one's life.
IG. The Right to Terminate One's Life
See "The Murder of Oneself".
IH. The Right to Have One's Life Terminated
The right to euthanasia
to have one's life terminated at will
is restricted by numerous social
ethical
and legal rules
principles
and considerations. In a nutshell - in many countries in the West one is thought to has a right to have one's life terminated with the help of third parties if one is going to die shortly anyway and if one is going to be tormented and humiliated by great and debilitating agony for the rest of one's remaining life if not helped to die. Of course
for one's wish to be helped to die to be accommodated
one has to be in sound mind and to will one's death knowingly
intentionally
and forcefully.
II. Issues in the Calculus of Rights
IIA. The Hierarchy of Rights
All human cultures have hierarchies of rights. These hierarchies reflect cultural mores and lores and there cannot
therefore
be a universal
or eternal hierarchy.
In Western moral systems
the Right to Life supersedes all other rights (including the right to one's body
to comfort
to the avoidance of pain
to property
etc.).
Yet
this hierarchical arrangement does not help us to resolve cases in which there is a clash of EQUAL rights (for instance
the conflicting rights to life of two people). One way to decide among equally potent claims is randomly (by flipping a coin
or casting dice). Alternatively
we could add and subtract rights in a somewhat macabre arithmetic. If a mother's life is endangered by the continued existence of a fetus and assuming both of them have a right to life we can decide to kill the fetus by adding to the mother's right to life her right to her own body and thus outweighing the fetus' right to life.
IIB. The Difference between Killing and Letting Die
There is an assumed difference between killing (taking life) and letting die (not saving a life). This is supported by IE above. While there is a right not to be killed - there is no right to have one's own life saved. Thus
while there is an obligation not to kill - there is no obligation to save a life.
IIC. Killing the Innocent
Often the continued existence of an innocent person (IP) threatens to take the life of a victim (V). By "innocent" we mean "not guilty" - not responsible for killing V
not intending to kill V
and not knowing that V will be killed due to IP's actions or continued existence.
It is simple to decide to kill IP to save V if IP is going to die anyway shortly
and the remaining life of V
if saved
will be much longer than the remaining life of IP
if not killed. All other variants require a calculus of hierarchically weighted rights. (See "Abortion and the Sanctity of Human Life" by Baruch A. Brody).
One form of calculus is the utilitarian theory. It calls for the maximization of utility (life
happiness
pleasure). In other words
the life
happiness
or pleasure of the many outweigh the life
happiness
or pleasure of the few. It is morally permissible to kill IP if the lives of two or more people will be saved as a result and there is no other way to save their lives. Despite strong philosophical objections to some of the premises of utilitarian theory - I agree with its practical prescriptions.
In this context - the dilemma of killing the innocent - one can also call upon the right to self defence. Does V have a right to kill IP regardless of any moral calculus of rights? Probably not. One is rarely justified in taking another's life to save one's own. But such behaviour cannot be condemned. Here we have the flip side of the confusion - understandable and perhaps inevitable behaviour (self defence) is mistaken for a MORAL RIGHT. That most V's would kill IP and that we would all sympathize with V and understand its behaviour does not mean that V had a RIGHT to kill IP. V may have had a right to kill IP - but this right is not automatic
nor is it all-encompassing.
Archives
-
▼
2009
(244)
-
▼
พฤษภาคม
(186)
- Female Health Sleep Patterns
- Female Hair Loss Treatment And Information
- Female Hair Loss And Menopause
- Female Bodybuilding
- Feeling Frisky Herbs For Fertility
- Feel Sexy with Larger Breasts the natural way
- Feather Boa For A Girls Night Out
- Fashion For Cruises
- Facts About Genital Warts
- Facial Mask At Home
- Extrasensory Perception Or ESP What Is It
- Exfoliate For Amazing Movie Star Skin
- Everything Midlife Women Would Like to Know about ...
- Enhancing Your Breasts Naturally
- Endometriosis and Hysterectomy Weigh The Risks
- Elegant Not Strangled
- Easy Breast Enlargement
- Easing Menstrual Cramps By Using Home Remedies
- Early Signs Of Menopause
- Early Menopause Symptoms
- Dry Skin Care Quiz
- Don t Be Afraid Of Dermatology
- Does Your Bra Fit Find The Right Size For Your Body
- Does Shaving Your Bikini Lines Drive You Bonkers
- Does Moon Really Influences Hair Growth Truth Beh...
- Does Menopause Last Long
- Do You Want A Sexy Perky Butt
- Do you have regular menstruation cycles
- Do Not Let Stretch Marks Invade Your Body
- Diy Skin Savers The Aspirin Mask
- Discovering Laser Hair Removal Side Effects
- Discover The Latest Hairstyles Before The Celebrities
- Dietary information when you are expecting
- Diamonds A Symbol Of Love And Romance
- Day Spas - The Perfect Pampering Experience
- Creative Breast Enhancement Techniques
- Crash Course On Cellulites
- CPR for Lackluster Libidos in Midlife
- Cosmetic Surgery Lifts and Jobs
- Cosmetic Surgery Will It Really Change Your Life
- Cosmetic Dentistry - A Perfect Smile
- Cosmetic Dentistry - A Closer Look
- Controversial Implants Approved
- Control Your Weight Change your LifeStyle
- Contemplating Breast Enhancement
- Contact Lenses - They Will Change Your Life No Do...
- Contact Lenses A Buyer s Guide
- Confidence And Poise Girls Do You Have It
- Conceiving A Baby And Conception Positions
- Common Pregnancy Complications
- Commercial Tanning Beds Pros And Cons
- Comfortable Tanning Bed Pillows
- Colour Cosmetics
- Colored Contacts As Easy As Hair Dye And Dieting.
- Color Determines The Tone Of Your Flowers Arrangem...
- Christian Dior Had Always Passion To Scents
- Choosing The Right Shampoo For Your Hair Type
- Choosing The Right Hair Dryer
- Choosing The Correct Sports Bra
- Choosing The Best Tanning Lotion For Your Skin
- Choosing Tanning Products Wisely
- Choosing Maternity Bras For Maximum Comfort And Su...
- Choosing And Caring For Contact Lenses
- Choosing A Wig - Find Your True Color
- Choosing A Wig - Face Shape Guide
- Choosing A Wig - Dispelling The Wig Myths
- Choosing A Moissanite Stone
- Choosing A Hair Removal System
- Choosing A Bikini
- Choosing Buying A Replica Handbag
- Chinese Medicine for PMS
- Chinese Medicine For Breast Health
- Chemical Peel Facts - Is It Right For You
- Cheap Home Alternatives To Off-The-Wall Bridal Mak...
- Characteristics in the physiology of female athletes
- Changing Your Mans Underwear And Getting Away With It
- Changing Your Look With Colored Contact Lenses
- Change Your Shopping Habits To Save Gas Save Mone...
- Chanel 5 And Other Perfumes Naming
- Cessation Menopause
- Cellulite Treatment Methods
- Celebrating Motherhood From The Coloring Room To ...
- Causes Of Stretch Marks
- Can You Imagine A Beautiful Life
- Can You Gender Test Your Unborn Child
- Can Women Build Big Muscles Why Women Can t Build...
- Can I Wear Contact Lenses If I Need Bifocals
- Buying A Ladies Handbag
- Building Better Bones
- Brittle Nails - Easy To Break
- Bridal Lingerie Considerations
- Bridal Lingerie Buying Guide
- Bridal Gowns How To Find The Perfect Wedding Dress
- Breast Pills Helps You to Lead the Race
- Breast Pills Effective in Improving the Growth of ...
- Breast Pills An Absolute Alternative for Surgery
- Breast Enlargement Results
- Breast Enlargement Procedures Types of Augmentatio...
- Breast Enlargement Procedures Breast Enlargement H...
- Breast Enlargement gives an Aura to your Body
-
▼
พฤษภาคม
(186)